Experience, crisis, structure

elementary problems of history and philosophy of psychology from a phenomenological perspective

Authors

DOI:

https://doi.org/10.62506/phs.v5i1.162

Keywords:

Epistemology, Phenomenology, Philosophy of Science, Structuralism, Thomas Kuhn

Abstract

In this theoretical essay, a confrontation is proposed between the thought of Thomas Kuhn, especially his analysis of the scientist's behavior and the epistemological matrices in The structure of scientific revolutions, and the phenomenological approach to the construction of knowledge, having as its center the ontological, methodological and epistemological situation of Psychology.  It is developed as a theoretical and argumentative essay, which develops five main argumentative lines through the confrontation of Kuhn's theses with those of authors of a phenomenological point of view.  At first, we try to demonstrate how normal thought, analyzed by Kuhn, has the same structure of meaning as naturalism, which seeks to be critically analyzed from a phenomenological perspective.  In a second moment, it is proposed that psychology does not portray a period of solving puzzles, of normal science, nor the stage of a “pre-paradigmatic science”, according to Kuhn's diagnostic criteria;  and that this approach is due to an attempt at an analogical foundation of Psychology, but which hides a philosophical prejudice.  Derived from this point, in a third moment, it is shown how the assumption of the alleged unity of Psychology, as a reality or as a goal, or, even, of its technical success, veils the question of the foundations of Psychology.  As a fourth argument, it analyzes how the disengagement between language and reality, or between concept and factuality, is usually read in terms of a “paradigm crisis” or “crisis of Psychology”, which, hypothetically, would require a therapy to correct the established problem.  Finally, it is argued that this disengagement, on the contrary, motivates a “change of attitude” on the part of the theorist in Psychology and, thus, requires him to deal with the problem of fundamentals.

References

Castañon, G. A. (2008). Filosofia como Fundamento e Fronteira da Psicologia, Ciências Humanas e Sociais em Revista, 30(1):10-18.

Heidegger, M. (2007). A questão da técnica, Scientiae Studia, 5(3): 375-98. Disponível em: < http://www.scientiaestudia.org.br/revista/PDF/05_03_05.pdf>.

Heidegger, M. (1993). Ser e tempo: parte I. (Márcia de Sá Cavalcante, trad.). Petrópolis: Vozes.

Husserl, E. (1989). Epilogue. In E Husserl. Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy. Second book: Studies in the phenomenology of constitution. (Richard Rojcewicz & André Schuwer, transl.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. (Originalmente publicado em 1930).

Husserl, E. (1993). Idées directrices pour une phénoménologie et un phénoménologie pure, livre III. (D. Diffeneau, trad.). Paris : Presses Universitaires de France.

Husserl, E. (2012). A crise das ciências europeias e a fenomenologia transcendental: uma introdução à filosofia fenomenológica. (Diogo Falcão Ferrer, Trad.). Rio de Janeiro: Forense Universitária.

Kuhn, T. S. (2006). Posfácio. In T. S. Kuhn. A estrutura das revoluções científicas (9a ed., B. Vianna Boeira & N. Boeira, trads.). São Paulo: Perspectiva.

Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 2nd. Ed. (International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, v. 2, no. 2). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Lacey, H. (2006). Relações entre fato e valor, Cadernos de Ciências Humanas, Especiaria, 9(16):251-266.

Lacey, H. (2009). O lugar da ciência no mundo dos valores e da experiência humana, Scientia Studia, 7(4):681-701.

Lacey, H. (2010). Valores e atividade científica, dois. São Paulo: Editora 34.

Loparic, Z. (1989). Paradigmas cartesianos, Cadernos de História e Filosofia da Ciência, 1(2):185-212, jul.-dez.

Merleau-Ponty, M. (2006). Fenomenologia da percepção. (Carlos Alberto Ribeiro de Moura, trad.). São Paulo: Martins Fontes. (Originalmente publicado em 1945).

Mülberger, A. (2012). Psicologia e crise: estudo de uma relação histórica. In S. F. Araújo (Org.). História e Filosofia da Psicologia: Perspectivas Contemporâneas. Juiz de Fora: Ed. UFJF.

Renaudie, P.-J. (2010). Rectitude et obliquité intentionnele de l’Oratio phénoménologique: Remarques croisées sur McDowell, Brentano et Husserl, Bulletin d’analyse phénoménologique, 8(3): 109-128.

Sowa, Rochus. (2009). Essences et lois d’essence dans l’eidétique descriptive de Edmund Husserl, (Véronique Decaix & Claudio Majolino, trad.), Methodos, 9. Disponível em: < https://journals.openedition.org/methodos/2214>. Acesso em 04 de dez. 2022.

Stam, H. J. (2004). Unifying Psychology: Epistemological Act or Disciplinary Maneuver?, Journal of Clinical Psychology, 60(12) :1259-1262.

Sturm, T., & Mülberger, A. (2012). Crisis discussions in psychology: New historical and philosophical perspectives, Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, (Special Issue: Crisis in Psychology), 43: 425-433.

Teo, T. (2010). Ontology and scientific explanation: Pluralism as an a priori condition of psychology, New Ideas in Psychology, 28: 235-243.

Thines, G. (1968). La problématique de la psychologie. La Haye: Martinus Nijhoff.

Thines, G. (1978). Fenomenología y ciencia de la conducta. Madrid: Ediciones Pirámide.

Verdan, A. (1998). O ceticismo filosófico. (Jaimir Conte, trad.). Florianópolis: Ed. UFSC.

Published

2024-02-09

How to Cite

Santos, H. P. D. (2024). Experience, crisis, structure: elementary problems of history and philosophy of psychology from a phenomenological perspective. Phenomenology, Humanities and Sciences, 5(1), 22–33. https://doi.org/10.62506/phs.v5i1.162